Saturday, 21 December 2019

Collective Obligations and Responsibility


Introduction – the mitzvah of Hakhel

Several of the mitzvos in the Torah are addressed to the Jewish People as a whole. I am not referring to the mitzvos which merely apply to every individual at all times, such as believing in G-d or loving a fellow Jew. While these mitzvos are enhanced tremendously when they are kept by multitudes, they have an inherent value even if observed by just one individual. I wish to discuss mitzvos which cannot be fulfilled by a single individual on any level and require communal observance.[1]

The clearest example is the mitzvah, of Hakhel, the gathering of the entire people during Sukkos in the year following Shemita to hear the reading of the Torah. If only one person wants to do this mitzvah and cannot persuade others to join, he will earn reward for trying but ultimately he will be exempt from the mitzvah.

Equally, if one individual decides not to come while the rest of the nation attends, the purpose of the mitzvah has arguably been fully achieved. While a separatist may lose out personally, the purpose of the mitzvah is not personal but communal. On a communal level, the effect of one individual not attending is usually negligible.[2]

The question I want to discuss is when the absentee is not a separatist and understands the value of the mitzvah, but comes to the conclusion that as his part in the mitzvah is negligible, he would be better off using his time differently. Obviously if everyone or a significant number of people came to the same conclusion, the purpose of the mitzvah would not be achieved, but why is this important? He is careful to make sure that no-one notices his absence, such that his decision will have no effect on anyone else's. Our instincts tell us that this is not acceptable, but at first glance it is not so easy to explain why.

The Chinuch writes that anyone who does not come at the relevant time to hear the Torah reading, or if the king cancels the reading, they violate this command and will bear a severe punishment.[3] In other words, the absconder is not just a sinner - he is in some way equivalent to a king who cancels the entire reading! Where did the Chinuch know this from?

The answer is that the Torah's command regarding the mitzvah of Hakhel inherently includes an obligation on every individual. This is not because the individual's contribution is necessarily significant; it may very well not be. It is simply because if there were no obligation on the individual, the command to the nation would be toothless.

Tax Evasion

Similar logic applies to other communal mitzvos such as Kriyas HaTorah and appointing a king.[4] However, most of the mitzvos of the Torah are not inherently communal. I would like to discuss how the addition of a communal aspect to these mitzvos affects their severity, if at all.

The crime of theft is a good example of a prohibition which is primarily individual.[5] One person who steals from another person is guilty of a serious transgression. It is also clearly possible to steal something which is jointly owned, or owned by the inhabitants of an entire city or country. Does this variation of the transgression carry a different level of severity to private theft?

On the one hand, one who steals 1,000 NIS from the average individual will likely cause a significant amount of distress; one who evades a similar amount in taxes (without anyone else noticing) will not make a significant difference to anyone else. On the other hand, if we were to apply a similar principle to that of the Chinuch above, considering it as if the tax evader was responsible for the equivalent damage had everyone acted similarly, he would be a far more serious criminal than the common thief.

It is however far from clear that this extrapolation is correct. A more severe punishment for one who steals public funds is not inherent in the command not to steal.[6] In this instance, logic would seem to dictate that a tax evader is equivalent to a simple thief and not any better or worse.[7]

Nevertheless, the Tosefta singles out public theft as being more severe than private theft for a technical reason. As one who steals from the public typically will not know who he has stolen from, he will also not be able to do teshuva to perfection.[8] Depending on the circumstances, a variation of this technical reason may also apply to tax evasion as it is not always easy to 'overpay' on taxes and persuade the authorities to accept the payment without a good explanation.

Elsewhere, Chazal list public theft as one of the sins that result in tzara'as afflictions.[9] Here no explicit reason is given, although it is likely that here too the reason is technical. The example given is that of Shevna, an official in the Beis Hamikdash who misappropriated sacred property.[10] The aspect that seems to warrant the punishment of tzara'as is the breach of trust given to the person, more than the communal nature of the theft.

Voting

Communal responsibility is perhaps more often an issue when it comes to actions we do which are not mitzvos in a clearly defined way, but which certainly are important on a large scale. Let's assume for the moment that the makeup of the Knesset (or parliaments elsewhere in the world) is something worth influencing.[11] We still need to explain why the individual, whose individual vote will almost certainly not have any influence, should bother voting (assuming that he does not publicise his actions and does not influence anyone else to vote or not to vote).

In other words, the question is whether or not to accept Kant's Categorical Imperative, which states that one should "act only according to that maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will that it should be a universal law."[12] According to this rule, as I wouldn't want all of those who vote the same way as I do to stay at home, I must not stay home myself (despite this having no effect).

The answer is that it depends on my motivation for willing a particular act to be a universal law. If this act is necessary on a communal level for the fulfilment of a command of the Torah, this command also inherently obligates each individual (for otherwise the command would be toothless, as described above). This is in general the perception of religious Jews when it comes to voting.[13]

If there is no Torah command that obligates a certain action, it is hard for me to see what does obligate it even on a communal level.[14] If an individual merely wants the government to do something for his own reasons, without believing in any obligation to do so, he certainly is not obligated to vote (according to his perception) and on a practical level there is probably also no point in doing so (unless he also influences others).

Personal Circumstances

Aside from the above, my major reservation with the Categorical Imperative is that rarely are one person's circumstances identical to another person's. If Kant meant that rules of conduct can have no exceptions based on the circumstances, I strongly disagree. One who needs to steal to save his life must certainly do so (and must pay back afterward when possible).[15]

Returning to the example of voting, I would agree that in general a person should vote even if he lives in an area where the vote will not be close (e.g. a non-swing state in the US or a safe seat for any party in the UK). However, someone whose circumstances mean that an abnormal effort is necessary in order to vote (e.g. he lives abroad and postal voting is difficult) should ask himself whether or not he would be happy for everyone in similar circumstances didn't vote. If the answer is yes, he need not make the effort.[16]


[1] Many of the ideas here have been adapted from this post (in Hebrew) and others by R' Michael Avraham, although I have also added a significant amount of my own input.
[2] Assuming that this person is not a significant influence on a significant number of people.
[3] Mitzvah 612.
[4] Each of these mitzvos have some organisational aspect which many individuals may not have to be part of; they fulfil their obligation by merely attending, consenting or paying dues. However, ultimately everyone is responsible for this aspect too and if no-one does it, all are to blame.
[5] While there may be some technical differences between various halachic categories of theft (גניבה, גזלה, עושק etc.), for the purposes of this post there is no difference. Similarly, I have used the word 'theft' and similar throughout, even where technically the correct English term may be 'fraud,' 'embezzlement' or evasion.
[6] The simple individual command not to steal is enough to give teeth to the application to public theft as well.
[7] In democratic countries today, taxes are in general communal funds and not the property of the king or government. One who evades paying is no different to a member of a private club who refuses to pay his dues. He has no right to the services that he receives, which are taken as a form of theft. This is all irrespective of whether or not 'Dina demalchusa' applies, or whether or not evading paying debts to non-Jews is forbidden.
[8] Bava Kama chapter 10.
[9] Vayikra Rabba, Parshas Metzora 17:3.
[10] See Yeshayahu 22:15-25
[11] I do not intend to state here whether I believe this is the case even when elections are held 3 times a year.
[12] Regarding non-Jewish philosophy as a whole, I already discussed the opposing views of the Rambam and Maharal in Wisdom of the Nations, a few years ago but also approaching Chanuka. Regular readers will probably not be surprised to learn that I subscribe to the position of the Rambam – I am in principle happy to accept enlightenment from whatever sources may be relevant. However, unlike with Torah, I do not see the value of spending large amounts of time ensuring that I have the correct understanding of the words of any particular philosopher. If I have completely misunderstood Kant then so be it – what is important is whether a particular philosophy is correct or not, whether or not Kant really meant it.
I do not mean to negate the value of studying philosophical works inherently – if I was sufficiently impressed by any philosopher's ability and intellectual honesty, I would spend more time trying to find gems within his words. This is no different to the way I approach the writings of our own commentators (both halachic and philosophical). If I have a question that bothers me and I see that several acharonim deal with it, I will usually only read the writings of those who in my experience are likely to give an answer that satisfies me. Although one can learn from anyone, there simply are not enough hours in the day or years to live to be able to read everything.
[13] We all may have different things that we think the government needs to do, but the thing that unites almost all Jews is the view that what I think needs to be done is also something that must be done.
[14] Even if there are morals which are not included in the Torah but I know intuitively (see Torah and Morals), what obligates me to be moral? If I intuitively know that Hashem wants me to do something, this would presumably be covered by mitzvos of the Torah such as ועשית הישר והטוב.
[15] See Bava Kama 60b and commentaries thereon.
[16] For this reason I did not vote in the recent UK elections – I did not believe that the number of those living in Israel with a right to a postal vote in my constituency would influence the local result. I did go to the minimal effort of registering for a postal vote, but did not make any arrangements for the event of the forms not arriving in time (to no great surprise, this is what happened).

Saturday, 30 November 2019

Leaving Eretz Yisrael


Introduction

In the global society that we live in, for many it is hard to come to terms with a prohibition which may 'imprison' us in one country. Even among those who were born in Eretz Yisrael, there are few who have never left.

In addition, for most of the last 2,000 years, for most of Jewry there was little practical ramification to this prohibition, and as a result the halachic literature on the topic was limited. Here I will try to clarify what exactly is included and why. There are apparent contradictions in this regard between at least three different passages in the gemara, which will need to be resolved.

1) Making a Living – Bava Basra 91a

The gemara quotes a Beraisa which says that we may not leave Eretz Yisrael unless there is a famine so bad that two se'ah (roughly 16 litres) of flour costs a sela (a silver coin weighing roughly 19g). R' Shimon argues that if one is able to buy, he must not leave even under these circumstances. Elimelech, Machlon and Chilyon all were punished for not heeding this requirement.

Later on, the gemara qualifies that those who are not able to earn money may leave, however cheap food may be. This 'leniency' is possibly the primary justification for living outside Eretz Yisrael to this day, as many of those who were educated outside of Israel would find it difficult to find a job here.[1]

Most of the rishonim assume that the halacha is not in accordance with the strict view of R' Shimon, and in times of severe famine it is permitted to leave, if strongly discouraged.[2] However, even according to this, from this gemara, the only dispensation that appears to be given is for those in some kind of financial difficulty.

2) Mitzvos versus Impurity – Avoda Zara 13a

Elsewhere it seems clear that there are some other reasons for which it is permitted to leave the country. Kohanim have an additional problem with being outside Eretz Yisrael – Chazal decreed that all of Chutz La'aretz is impure.[3] This would normally mean that kohanim cannot leave Eretz Yisrael,[4] although a beraisa gives 3 reasons for which a kohen is allowed to become 'contaminated' with this kind of impurity:

  • To retrieve one's money or property in court.
  • To learn Torah.[5]
  • To get married.

It seems rather strange that these reasons are not mentioned at all by the first gemara quoted. Furthermore, the implication here is that these special circumstances are only necessary in order to allow a kohen to leave Eretz Yisrael. The impression given is that a regular Jew could leave even without such a pressing need.

3) Deserving of Death – Kesuvos 111a

A person once asked R' Chanina if he should leave Eretz Yisrael in order to perform the mitzvah of yibum, after his brother died there leaving a widow and no children. R' Chanina answered rhetorically in the third person: "His brother married a Kuthean[6] and died, Baruch Hashem who killed him! Now he (the questioner) should follow him?!"[7]

Here R' Chanina warns someone (not specifically identified as a kohen) not to leave Eretz Yisrael even for the purpose of marrying and performing the extra mitzvah of yibum.

To summarise, the different impressions one gets from the 3 sections of the gemara are:

1) It is permitted to leave only out of financial necessity.
2) One may leave in order to perform one of various important mitzvos, including getting married.
3) One may not leave in order to get married.

Gemara 2) seems to be contradicted by both 1) and 3).

Resolution

Tosfos[8] raise the issue of the contradiction between 2) and 3), and are forced to explain that the dispensation to leave Eretz Yisrael to marry in 2) is only temporary – the plan must be to return after the mitzvah is done. In 3), the enquiry was about leaving permanently.

This explanation appears rather difficult, as in neither 2) nor 3) does the gemara specify whether the intention was to return or not. As in both places the gemara is dealing with someone wanting to leave in order to perform a specific task, I believe it is fair to assume that in both instances the leniency is only regarding leaving temporarily. Furthermore, getting married would not appear to justify leaving Eretz Yisrael permanently, as the halacha entitles either spouse to insist on moving to Eretz Yisrael.[9]

The Rambam makes the same distinction as Tosfos, although he seems to do this based on 1) and 2) above as opposed to 2) and 3). He writes that while it is permitted to leave Eretz Yisrael temporarily in order to learn, marry etc., (2), leaving permanently can only be justified out of severe financial need (1).[10] The grounding for this approach in the gemara is clearer to me – the global conditions such as famine and economy described in gemara 1) have no clear endpoint and one who leaves for this reason cannot usually make clear plans to return.

If my thesis is correct, the Rambam does not accept the explanation of Tosfos regarding gemara 3). Here it was wrong to leave Eretz Yisrael even temporarily, even in order to perform yibum. I believe that in 3) there was a special reason – the late brother originally left Eretz Yisrael without any justification and bore the consequences. To honour the memory of such a person by following in his footsteps, even temporarily, is not recommended. The surviving brother may have already had a wife, and even if he didn't he would do better finding one in Eretz Yisrael.[11]

Business Trips

The remaining difficulty is the implication from 2) that a non-kohen may leave Eretz Yisrael (albeit temporarily) for reasons other than the 3 listed. The Rambam resolves this difficulty by adding a fourth reason that a non-kohen may leave Eretz Yisrael temporarily – in order to do business.9

The probable source for this leniency is a fourth gemara, dealing with the prohibition of shaving during Chol HaMo'ed. This prohibition is waived for various people who were not able to shave before Yom Tov; the tana'im dispute whether one who returns from abroad is included in this leniency. The gemara explains that all agree that for one who went on a pleasure trip there is no leniency and all agree that one who goes in order to obtain sustenance may shave on his return. The dispute is regarding one left in order to 'make a profit,' with R' Yehuda ruling stringently and the Chachamim permitting.[12] The halacha follows the Chachamim.[13]

The dispensation given for one who returns from a business trip is a clear indication that such trips are permitted. The Rambam uses the same language (לסחורה) to describe such trips, both in reference to the prohibition of leaving Eretz Yisrael and when quoting the leniency during Chol HaMo'ed.[14]

Equivalent Reasons

The rishonim dispute whether the circumstances listed by the gemara allowing one to leave are exhaustive. Tosfos quote the view of Rav Achai Ga'on, that the 3 reasons listed in the gemara are relatively weak.[15] It goes without saying that it is permitted to leave in order to fulfil other mitzvos. Tosfos disagree, showing that elsewhere these mitzvos are given a higher priority than other mitzvos.[16]

The Rambam writes that the reasons listed above allowing a kohen to leave Eretz Yisrael are examples, and the same applies for similar reasons.[17] Regarding a regular Jew, the Rambam gives the four exceptions (litigation, learning, marrying and business) and does not state explicitly that these are mere examples. However, this is presumably because the leniency of leaving in order to do business is by definition wide-ranging. It would be inconceivable to suggest that leaving Eretz Yisrael temporarily is permitted for business, but not in order to perform mitzvos.

The conclusion is that for a non-kohen, leaving Eretz Yisrael temporarily is permitted for any mitzvah purpose or for anything akin to 'business.'[18] Leaving for pleasure alone would appear to be forbidden.

Rationale

Rashbam writes that the reason that Chazal forbade leaving Eretz Yisrael is because leaving absolves a person of the mitzvos connected to the land.[19] Ramban explains differently, that all the hyperbole used by Chazal in relation to Eretz Yisrael is part of the mitzvah of taking possession and living in Eretz Yisrael.[20]

Following either approach, it is hard to understand why it would be forbidden to take a short trip to see some of the wonders of creation (or even the wonders of different societies) outside of Eretz Yisrael while intending to return. It is likely that the original reason that Chazal were so stringent was because in the past, plans to return even after a short period of time would often not materialise. Nowadays this seems far less relevant.

Some poskim are indeed more lenient nowadays based on this difference.[21] However, without a Sanhedrin to rescind or alter the prohibition, this is far from straightforward.[22] It is quite clear from cases in the gemara that the prohibition applies even when stepping over the border for a minute.[23]

My conclusion therefore is that one thinking about travelling out of Eretz Yisrael for pleasure should consider carefully whether this is really necessary, and whether he could not make alternative plans at one of the many potential locations inside the country. Those who are uncomfortable with the perhaps anachronistic nature of the prohibition could find comfort in the fact that nowadays there is a new reason to limit travel – doing our bit for preserving the planet by reducing carbon emissions.


[1] It is very difficult to define what level of effort a person must put in in order to overcome this problem, although for those who do not currently live in Eretz Yisrael it makes sense to be fairly leninent.
[2] Rambam, Hilchos Melachim 5:9; Yad Rama. See also Meiri.
[3] See Shabbos 15a-b for details of the various decrees. The main reason for this enactment seems to have been practical – there were many unidentified graves in Chutz La'aretz which a kohen may come in contact with unintentionally. However, see Tosfos in Nazir 54b (ד"ה ארץ העמים) who give an additional purpose – Chazal wanted to discourage us from leaving.
[4] The poskim discuss whether this applies nowadays, the Maharshal claiming that now Eretz Yisrael is no less pure than the rest of the world (commentary on the Tur, Yoreh Deah 369). See Shach, Taz and Pischei Teshuva to Yoreh Deah 369:1.
[5] The tana'im dispute whether this applies when there are rabbis in Eretz Yisrael from whom a person could learn. The halacha follows R' Yossi, who allows one to go to learn outside Eretz Yisrael even in these circumstances. The reasoning is that a person is not necessary capable of learning successfully from anyone.
[6] See Maharsha in Chidushei Agados who explains why this term was used here.
[7] Kesuvos 111a
[8] Avoda Zara 13a (ד"ה ללמוד)
[9] See Mishna and gemara, Kesuvos 110b.
[10] Hilchos Melachim 5:9
[11] See Chidushei Maharit on the gemara there, who explains similarly. The mitzvah of yibum does not obligate him to travel – it is incumbent on the widow to come to the place of the brother-in-law for yibum or chalitza (Sanhedrin 31b).
[12] Mo'ed Katan 14a
[13] See Shulchan Aruch, Orach Chaim 531:4
[14] Hilchos Yom Tov 7:18
[15] See Yad P'shuta, Hilchos Avel 3:14 who explains that this is not because learning and marrying are less important than other mitzvos, just that it is far from certain that these objectives will be met by leaving.
[16] Avoda Zara 13a (ד"ה ללמוד). The proof is from the prohibition of selling a Sefer Torah, which is only waived if the purpose is to learn or marry. However, according to the Yad P'shuta this can be resolved. Selling a Sefer Torah can raise the funds needed immediately, whereas undertaking a long journey in order to do these mitzvos is far less assured of being successful.
[17] Hilchos Avel 3:14
[18] As R' Shaul Yisraeli points out in Eretz Chemda 1:1:10, even Tosfos only limited the leniencies given to a kohen and did not discuss the law of a non-kohen. The conclusion of the gemara in Kidushin 31b also seems to be that it is permitted to leave Eretz Yisrael in order to honour ones parents.
[19] Bava Basra 91a (ד"ה אין יוצאין). This reason requires further explanation, as one is not usually obligated to ensure that he becomes liable to perform mitzvos. Furthermore, Hashem decided that these mitzvos should not apply outside Eretz Yisrael for a reason. Assuming that the reason was to highlight the importance of Eretz Yisrael, it would appear that the Rashbam has paradoxically made the means (the mitzvos) dependent on the end purpose (living in Eretz Yisrael).
[20] Sefer HaMitzvos, 'forgotten' positive mitzvah 4
[21] See Peninei Halacha, "The People and the Land," 3:9
[22] I discussed this at length in Eternal or Obsolete.
[23] See for example Gitin 76b.

Friday, 8 November 2019

Killing to save - the law of the rodef


I am sure that most readers will be aware that the Torah encourages the prevention of murder by virtually all means, including taking the life of the would-be murderer (or rodef, pursuer) when absolutely necessary.[1] Here I would like to examine the application of this 'leniency' in a variety of cases, after the following disclaimer:

The misuse of these halachos by a certain individual in recent history has led some to make discussion of the entire subject a taboo. I, however, believe that intelligent analysis of any topic is not to be silenced in any way. For those who are exceptionally sensitive to these issues at this time of year, read on at your own risk. For those who are not, don't be disappointed if what I write does not appear particularly controversial.

The unwitting pursuer

The first point to clarify is the status of a person endangering someone else's life unintentionally. The gemara tells us that if a child is about to kill someone, the child's life can (and should) be taken, without any warning (obviously, this is again only if this is the only way of saving the 'pursued').[2]

From here the acharonim infer that the main purpose of killing the pursuer is in order to save the pursued, rather than being a punishment.[3] However, even after this explanation, I have a great difficulty understanding why we are supposed to prioritise the life of the pursued over the pursuer when both are innocent. Wouldn't it be better to be passive, in the same way that we would normally kill one person in order to save another?

I have not seen anyone who addresses this question, and the only answer I have come up with myself is that in fact the gemara is not talking about a completely innocent pursuer. Although children are not usually held responsible for their actions, if a child is attempting murder we have a legitimate reason for deciding that "the blood of the victim is redder."

A corollary of this would be that if it is clear beyond doubt that the child is completely innocent, for example the 'pursuer' is a baby playing with a pistol, we have no right to terminate his life to save another.[4] The same would apply to an adult who is about to kill someone inadvertently, at least if it is clear that there is no negligence whatsoever involved.[5]

Foetal pursuers

The problem with this theory is that the gemara continues by comparing to a case where the life of a woman in childbirth is in danger, and could be saved by terminating the life of the foetus. The halacha is that as long as the baby's head has not emerged, the mother's life takes precedence. Once the baby is born, we do not "push off one life for another."

The gemara asks why isn't the newborn baby considered a 'rodef,' and therefore be killed to save the mother. This question clearly assumes that the status of a rodef can apply even to someone who is at no fault whatsoever.

The gemara answers that the usual law of a rodef does not apply in the case of the mother and baby, as "the pursual is from Heaven." Could the reasoning behind this cryptic answer be the hypothesis suggested above – as the baby has no responsibility whatsoever, his actions are not considered his own rather those of Heaven?

To my disappointment, I have not managed to find a single commentary that explains in this manner. The Rambam writes that once the baby has emerged he cannot be considered a rodef as "this is the nature of the world."[6] Apparently, the Rambam understands that a person cannot be deemed a rodef when acting in the normal way of the world.[7] One acting abnormally could be a rodef, even if they could not be expected to act with any degree of responsibility.

The Rid (Rabbeinu Yeshaya d'Trani, 1180-1260, Italy) writes that the baby is not a rodef as he is not acting on his own accord.[8] This is slightly closer to the way I would like to explain, although I believe that there is a difference. I understand that the Rid sees the baby during birth (even after the head has emerged) as akin to a stone being thrown, as his role in endangering the mother is entirely passive. If a baby was actively endangering someone, he would be considered a rodef despite not being at any fault.[9]

Indirect causes of danger

The next question is over the status of one who is not going to be the killer, but will facilitate the acts of the real murderer. If a witness to this cannot directly stop the murderer directly, should he foil his plans by eliminating the accomplice?

The answer to this would appear to be a simple yes. The gemara says that a moser (informant) is to be put to death, and quotes cases where this was indeed implemented. The reasoning is that once a person falls into the hands of an evil regime, even over monetary issues, his life will likely be in danger (this clearly does not apply to civilised governments nowadays).[10]

It is important to point out that this equation between a murderer and a facilitator of murder only applies before the murder has been committed (or if there is a danger of further murders taking place). After the fact, although a murderer may be liable to the death penalty,[11] an accomplice or even one who murdered indirectly alone (e.g. by stealing someone's life saving medicine) is not.[12] What is the reason for this distinction?

I once heard from R' Zalman Nechemia Goldberg (shlit"a) that the reason why the Torah does not obligate a person for damage caused indirectly is entirely practical. While an indirect damager (or killer) may be just as guilty as a direct one, if we had to punish indirect offenders it would be very difficult to define who exactly is considered a cause. In the end, we may have punished those with only spurious connections to the damage.[13]

This concern also exists when it comes to prevention of potential murder. However, when a human life is potentially in immediate danger, we do not have the option of simply remaining passive out of concern for what might happen in other situations. We must be decisive, and if it is clear beyond reasonable doubt that we can prevent murder, we must act. Equally, we must not make rash decisions to act without thinking it through properly.

Self-confidence and overconfidence

What happens when a person has thought out the issue properly and arrived at the conclusion that there is a rodef who must be disposed of, but no-one else seems to agree? He consults with others, hears their views but finds fault with their arguments that they are unable to address to his satisfaction. Is he supposed to defer to the majority opinion, or follow his own logic?

If we were dealing with a more 'run of the mill' halachic question, as long as there is no Sanhedrin I have written before that each person indeed has the right to 'go it alone.'[14] The same would seem to apply here, the only difference being that the severity of the issue would require more thorough consideration.

However, for technical reasons there will likely be a further difference here. Based on what we have already written, in order to classify someone as an indirect rodef and to kill him, the 'saviour' would need to be convinced that the following are all true:

1) The 'rodef' is definitely (beyond reasonable doubt) putting others in danger.
2) Nothing other than killing the 'rodef' will prevent this danger.
3) Killing the 'rodef' will stop this danger.[15]

The third condition will be much harder to fulfil if the 'saviour' is not recognised by others as preventing a real danger. As long as the 'rodef' has significant support, and even his opposition do not see him as a 'rodef,' it will likely be impossible for the one 'enlightened' individual to remove the danger alone. While one should not be scared of expressing unique opinions, one who does so should be well aware of the limits of his ability to draw others with him.

For those of us more inclined to fly in the face of public consensus, this last point is important to remember even with matters that are not an issue of life and death (or appear not to be). Individuals who act alone should usually do so only when others are not affected. Likewise, those in positions of power should respect the will of those they are representing when making far-reaching and irreversible decisions. Failure to do so often brings results that are unwanted by all.


[1] If the victim can be saved while also sparing the life of the rodef, such as by shooting him in the foot, this must be done (see Sanhedrin 57a).
[2] Sanhedrin 72b
[3] See for example Aruch LaNer, Sanhedrin 73a.
[4] See Chashukei Chemed, Sanhedrin 72b, who questions whether the baby is considered a 'rodef' here for other reasons.
[5] This may even be the implication of the language that the gemara uses, that a rodef can be killed even without warning. If he can be killed even when he is at no fault whatsoever, we would have expected the gemara to say so explicitly.
[6] Hilchos Rotzeach 1:9
[7] Although according to the Rambam there, an unborn foetus is considered a rodef even when merely following natural processes, as it is not yet a 'soul.' See also Igros Moshe, Choshen Mishpat 2:69.
[8] Piskei Rid, Sanhedrin 72b
[9] The Yerushalmi gives a different (and perhaps even more cryptic) reason not to kill the baby as a rodef – "it is not known who is killing who" (Shabbos 14:4, Avoda Zara 2:2). This presumably means that the mother is also endangering the baby as much as the baby is endangering her (although see Igros Moshe ibid. who explains that the Yerushalmi means the same as the Bavli). This also contradicts my hypothesis, stating that both the mother and baby are potential 'pursuers' despite the clear fact that neither have any guilt.
[10] Bava Kama 117a; Berachos 58a. See also Rosh to Bava Kama there, who writes explicitly that a moser is a type of rodef.
[11] If he was warned, verbally acknowledged that he will be liable to death and was witnessed by two kosher witnesses.
[12] There is some discussion about this regarding a moser (see Choshen Mishpat 388:11), although this is because of the concern that the moser may repeat his actions.
[13] He based this on the Rambam, who explains that the Torah does not accept circumstantial evidence for similar reasons (Sefer Hamitzvos, Lo Sa'aseh 290).
[15] It is not clear to me how definite one has to be about this – it would seem reasonable that one who sees someone beating another to death does not have to ensure 100% that it is not too late to save the victim.